top of page

My research has historically focused on Immanuel Kant’s philosophy, interpreting it as an organic, systematic whole that harmoniously combines theoretical and practical philosophy. In it, I offer a particular interpretation of the foundations of Kant’s critical philosophy and of the way Kant’s natural and moral philosophies build on these foundations to provide a “twofold metaphysics” of nature and morals. I argue that on the basis of this twofold metaphysics, Kant paints a majestic picture of the moral and political relations between humans as importantly analogous to the geometric and physical relations between bodies.

Beyond Kant, I have a wide variety of philosophical interests, both historical and contemporary including bioethics (with an emphasis on the social determinants of health), the history of ethics, science, logic, and revolutionary movements, the dynamics of complex systems, the philosophical and scientific use of mathematical methods, the psychology and biology of our emotions, and pragmatist/inferentialist views in the philosophy of language that explain the meaning of concepts and theories in terms of their use/the inferential role they play in our lives. I’m especially interested in the intersection of metaphysics, ethics/political philosophy, social theory, and the philosophy of science.

Currently, my work weaves together many of my interests to argue for and articulate a radical paradigm shift in ethical theory and practice. I argue that mainstream approaches to ethics are structurally incapable of solving the problems we face today and in actuality only serve to reinforce an unacceptable status quo. These approaches can be characterized as conducting ethics in a neutralizing vacuum. They abstract (to different degrees) away from the rich texture of embodied and embedded moral life and its messy conditions (e.g., social, economic, and political ones) for the sake of theoretical tractability and methodological and political neutrality. By doing so, however, these approaches alienate ethics from its connection to lived experience and thereby fail to realize its power to transform our lives and the world and render it susceptible to ideological corruption that turns it into a tool used to justify intolerable existing conditions. To unlock its transformative and liberating potential, we need to bring ethics down to Earth. We must ground ethics by connecting it to the current lived experience and conditions of people suffering in a planet that is being killed by human activity despite the fact that we have more resources than ever before. 

I argue that this vital grounding transformation requires a paradigm shift in ethics that is importantly analogous to the shift from classical to relativistic treatments of gravity. This latter paradigm shift in physics required realizing how physical phenomena couple to the medium of space-time in order to see how they condition and are conditioned by this medium. Analogously, the paradigm shift I argue for in ethics requires realizing how ethical phenomena couple to the medium in which they exist such that they condition and are conditioned by it. By focusing on this coupling of phenomena and medium, the paradigm shift I propose thereby brings ethics down to Earth, embedding ethical theory and practice in the complex, multidimensional world as it is actually experienced by persons struggling under a variety of social, economic, and political systems of oppression that deny their agency and full potential. Adequately developing this new paradigm requires adopting a transdisciplinary approach to ethics that brings in and weaves together tools from the full spectrum of disciplines to make sense of the complex ethical phenomena on Earth.

In articulating this framework, I build on and am inspired by the work of a wide variety of thinkers and doers past and present including Kant but also Zera Yacob, Friedrich Nietzsche, Karl Marx, Cedric Robinson, Audre Lorde, Kimberle Crenshaw, Michael Friedman, Fred D’Agostino, Judith Butler, Jenann Ismael, Anat Matar, Leah Lakshmi Piepzsna-Samarasinha, Heather McGhee, and more.

 

Publications

"Kant and the Balance of Moral Forces," Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy (forthcoming)

ABSTRACT: In the Doctrine of Virtue, Kant draws an analogy between the physical and moral worlds, claiming that love is a form of moral attraction, respect a form of moral repulsion, and that "should either of these great moral forces fail, then nothingness (immorality) with gaping throat would swallow up the whole realm of moral beings like a drop of water" (6:449). I argue that we can make sense of this intriguing yet puzzling passage by interpreting Kant here as employing a certain use of symbols/ analogies (developed in other critical works) that makes supersensible objects intuitive in a sense by symbolizing them with an analogous sensible object. Based on that, I argue that we should read this passage as endorsing a moral version of the balancing argument from his natural philosophy. There, Kant argues that purely repulsive and attractive bodies respectively face problems of total dispersion and collapse. I argue that purely respectful and loving humans respectively face analogous problems of total moral dispersion and collapse. I conclude by drawing some significant implications of this moral balancing argument for contemporary theorizing about moral interactions, relationships, and communities.

"On Kant's Derivation of the Categories," Kant-Studien (2018)

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I put forth a novel interpretation of how the third categories under each heading in the table of categories (totality, limitation, community, and necessity) are derived. Drawing on a passage from the first Critique and a letter to Schultz, I argue that in order to derive these categories, a special act of the understanding is required. I propose that we interpret this special act as consisting of an application of the third logical function under the corresponding heading that unites the combination of the first and second categories (under that same heading) so as to produce the third. 

Work in Progress

"Making the Supersensible Intuitive"

ABSTRACT: In this companion paper, I flesh out my interpretation of the species of use of symbols/analogies that Kant uses to make the supersensible objects of ideas intuitive in a sense by symbolizing them with an analogous sensible object. I then apply this interpretation to show how, by means of such analogies, Kant legitimizes the use of certain ideas that are central to both his theoretical philosophy (e.g., ground and substance) and moral philosophy (e.g., moral community and realm of ends).

"Bringing Ethics Down to Earth"

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I articulate a transdisciplinary framework for thinking about the mediums in which ethical phenomena play out. In doing so, I give a nonreductive metaphysics of ethical phenomena that locates them not just within a scientifically informed vision of the natural world but also within a humane margin-centering vision of an inherently unjust and deeply asymmetrical social world (one that privileges the perspectives and experiences of a variety of marginalized persons). By articulating this framework, I sketch a picture of some of the different mediums in which ethical phenomena play out and interact. I argue that this picture vividly highlights the need to cultivate an empathetic framework that can help us talk about and across the deep differences in our experience of the same physical world and the ethical phenomena within it in order to tackle the pressing social and moral problems that we face.

"Designing a Good Life"

ABSTRACT: In their Designing Your Life, Bill Burnett and Dave Evans from Stanford University combine insights and methods from design, positive psychology, and other disciplines to craft a "life design” framework that has been used by thousands of people to effectively transform their lives into happier, more meaningful, more resilient ones. I argue that by bringing together this framework with ethical theorizing we can develop a “good life design” framework that we can use to empirically evaluate and thereby enrich our ethical theorizing. More specifically, I show how we can refine life design’s “good time journal” to craft a “good life journal” that we can use to gather data about the value of activities that make up our lives. We can then use this journal to test whether particular “good life hypotheses/prototypes" (i.e., miniature experiments in living) actually constitute changes that make our lives, on the whole, better and use the data we gather to iteratively test and refine our good life hypotheses/prototypes. This framework thus frames social and moral problems as “wicked problems” in the designer’s sense (problems that are resistant to solution because they have many interdependent factors that are hard to define, incomplete, and constantly changing) and correspondingly combines tools from design thinking together with ethical concepts and theories to tackle them in more human-centered, iterative, and effective ways.

 

"Interacting Ethical Fields: The Coupled Dynamics of The Good, The Right, and Moral Worth"

ABSTRACT: Following John Rawls, we can characterize moral theory as the study of how the basic notions of the good, the right, and moral worth may be arranged to form different moral structures. Some philosophers try to explain which of these notions is more fundamental, trying to derive/reduce some from/to others. In this paper, I take a different strategy in connecting these different moral notions, one that relates them dynamically. I argue that we can understand the way these ethical notions relate as analogous to the way electricity and magnetism relate to each other. Thus, I advance a view on which we can understand axiological phenomena (encompassed by the good), deontic phenomena (encompassed by the right), and aretaic phenomena (encompassed by moral worth) as manifestations of axiological, deontic, and aretaic fields that dynamically couple to each other (analogously to how electric and magnetic fields do).

"A Kantian's Guide to Objective Morality"

ABSTRACT: This paper builds on Ismael’s “An Empiricist’s Guide to Objective Modality” (which itself builds on Lewis’s “A Subjectivist’ Guide to Objective Chance) in telling a sensible story about metaphysically puzzling concepts and their use. I argue that by following Ismael’s suggestion that we take a “side-on view” of the practices in which we use concepts, we open up room for a robust, non-reductive naturalism that naturalistically locates not just modal properties and relations but also ethical and moral properties and relations within a scientific vision of the world. In particular, it locates them not as (either reified or reduced) patterns in the mind-independent categorical manifold of events but as objective structures that encode information about how creatures with our practical, affective, social, and political capacities relate to patterns in this categorical manifold. 

"Naturalizing Transcendental Idealism"

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that a version of transcendental idealism can be seen to emerge from an attractive, naturalistic way of viewing the human mind as a certain kind of dynamical system that represents itself and governs its behavior by means of its self-representations. According to this naturalistic approach (which is articulated in different ways in the work of Craig Callender, Rick Grush, Jenann Ismael, and Huw Price among others) the embodied human mind not only passively receives sensory information from disparate sensory sources but also actively synthesizes information from these sensory sources into a global model of its environment. The mind represents itself in this model and uses it to navigate its environment. This view of the mind constitutes a version of transcendental idealism insofar as it accepts the two constitutive theses of transcendental idealism, roughly (TI-1): the things we experience are not things in themselves but rather representations that we synthesize from sensory information, and (TI-2): space and time are not features of mind-independent reality but rather primarily forms of sensibility, representational frameworks we use to coordinate different sensations.

"No Reversal in Kant's Foundational Moral Works"

ABSTRACT: A common interpretation of Kant's foundational moral works is that in the Critique of Practical Reason, Kant rejects his argument from Groundwork III and reverses his strategy of justification, arguing from morality to freedom rather than from freedom and the moral law. I argue, contrary to this interpretation, that the arguments from these two works are different kinds of argument, which are not incompatible but in fact complementary. The Groundwork argues that freedom is the ground of the possibility of the moral law, while the second Critique argues instead that consciousness of the moral law is the ground of cognition of freedom. Each argument aims to establish a different kind of conclusion, but together they make possible cognition not just that we must be free if our being bound by the moral law is to be possible but that we are actually free.

bottom of page